Jump to content
IndiaDivine.org

Overriding Passion

Rate this topic


Guest guest

Recommended Posts

The Institute of Science in Society

Science Society Sustainability

http://www.i-sis.org.uk

 

General Enquiries sam

Website/Mailing List press-release

ISIS Director m.w.ho

===================================================

 

ISIS review

***********

 

Overriding Passion

******************

 

Dr. Mae-Wan Ho reviews Behalf, by P.N. Furbank, University of Nebraska Press,

Lincoln & London, 1999. ISBN: 0-8032-2009-X

No one, it seems to me, who works in political advocacy of one form or another,

will fail to ask themselves from time to time: why am I doing all this? Who am I

doing it on behalf of?

The answer is not easy. But how better to find out than by following the

meanderings of Nick Furbank, the purveyor of an exquisite literary garden of

western thought, an oasis in the midst of the intellectual desert that’s our

present modernist culture.

Here, the trite word-merchants and peddlers of clichés are banished. The

artificers who argue night for day, the categorisers who reduce full-blooded

ideas to dry dust, the pontificators, the poseurs, all exposed and excised with

the fine precision of keyhole surgery.

From the first words, Furbank has you in thrall. You follow him down the

labyrinthine garden path, to marvel at the flowerings of thought through the

ages. You begin to appreciate the subtle shades of colours that make a world of

difference, the exquisite layering of petals that conceal an ocean of meaning

within. And just when you think you’ve got the answer, he looks you in the eye,

and turns to show you another, more seductive patch that you’ve completely

missed.

Should we share with Marcel Proust, the idea that each human being comprises,

potentially, characteristics of the whole human species? Or D.H. Lawrence’s

declaration, “The ultimate passion of every man is to be within himself the

whole of mankind”? When we use terms like “bourgeoisie” or the “proletariat”,

are we excluding ourselves from the narrative as though it referred to the

purely other? Are there things that no one is in a position to say?

For example, Wordsworth, in his poem, “Old Cumberland Beggar” pleads against

imprisoning a destitute old vagrant in a workhouse, “and its arguments are these

(was a more selfish set of reasons ever propounded?). The beggar makes us count

our own blessings and realize how well off we are. He encourages us to perform

our little acts of charity ...[and] we are to let him struggle picturesquely

with cold winds and winter snows because the hope in his heart is an emotion

worthy of reverence.”

That reminds me of arguments I’ve heard, against introducing labour-saving

devices such as the bicycle into poor villages which would spare women and

children having to fetch and carry water on foot, on grounds that it would ruin

their pristine indigenous culture.

Who has a right to say what, and from what position? Wittgenstein said, “Only a

very unhappy man has the right to pity someone else.”

If one is a woman, must one be a feminist? Or if gay or lesbian, a gay/lesbian

rights activist? Should one instead be a humanist, advocate pluralism, or the

politics of the person? And what do people mean when they speak of “humanity”?

According to Oxford political philosopher Isaiah Berlin, Johann Gottfried von

Herder was the inventor of pluralism as a doctrine: “The belief not merely in

the multiplicity, but in the incommensurability, of the values of different

cultures and societies and, in addition, in the incompatibility of equally valid

ideals, together with the implied revolutionary corollary that the classical

notions of a ideal man and of an ideal society are intrinsically incoherent and

meaningless.”

But Furbank does not find this “pluralism” or “incommensurability” of cultures

convincing. At least partly to blame for the rise of “pluralism” is the notion

that people have more or less completely lost any understanding of morality. As,

after some cataclysmic upheaval, we continue to use ethical terms but have lost

all grasp of the conceptual scheme that gave them their significance.

Aristotle’s concept of “the good life”, for example, comes before the concept of

a virtue. The “good life” is essentially social: it is a “practice with goods

internal to itself”, involving a notion of the “narrative unity” of a human

being’s practice and the quest for the good. By contrast with this coherently

ordered system, incoherence reigns and “pluralism threatens to submerge us all”.

“Indeed the process of moral debate today is only a masquerade”, says Furbank,

“for underlying it is the view that there are, and can be, no “unassailable

criteria” for resolving moral issues.”

Aristotle, following Plato, holds that the virtues are unified and inseparable,

flourishing side-by-side harmoniously and without conflict in the character of

the ‘good man’. Of course, there can be tragic, irresolvable, conflicts of

values. The virtues on which Aristotle perhaps lays most emphasis are Justice

and Friendship. And “what could be more obvious - more familiar to everyone’s

experience in whatever society, including the city-states of ancient Greece,”

Furbank asks, “than that the claims of justice are sometimes going to clash

painfully with the claims of friendship?”

Herder rejects the single overarching standard of values, in terms of which all

cultures, characters, and acts can be evaluated. “Each phenomenon to be

investigated presents its own measuring rod, its own internal constellation of

values in the light of which alone ‘the fact’ can be truly understood.”

But this assumes that each culture has a ‘measuring rod’, or ideal. Furbank

questions Berlin’s idea that Western thought has been dominated by the theory

that there is a single ideal way of life dedicated to a single supreme value in

which all other values are subsumed. “What was Classical polytheism [there being

many gods] but the personification of many and contrary values?” Furbank asks.

Perhaps Berlin is just saying that each culture has to be understood in its own

terms and in the light of its own values, it is about understanding and not

evaluation or judgement.

“But then, does it mean that the ethnographer must pass no criticism on

cruelty, injustice, and deprivation, just because they occur in another society,

and even though members of that society protest against them themselves?” asks

Levi-Strauss.

Fortunately, Levi-Strauss says that the dilemma is not really so complete, and

there is a way out. First, no society is perfect, even in its own eyes: every

society fails to live up to its own proclaimed norms that would judge a given

act as “an injustice, insensibility, or cruelty”. And when a large number of

societies are compared, one finds that no society is without certain advantages

of its members and also that the dose of “impurity” or “iniquity” in societies

tend to be fairly constant.

Human beings, says Levi-Strauss, are born social, and all humankind have the

same task - to find the formula of a liveable society. Getting to know other

societies is a way of detaching ourselves from our own, in order to help

identify the principles of social existence, to apply them to reform our own.

Thus, far from affirming the incomparability of culture, Levi-Strauss attaches

the highest importance to comparing them and to discerning in them various

“likenesses-across-a-difference”.

Herder’s Yet Another Philosophy of History proclaims that each of the natural

societies contains within itself the “ideal of its own perfection, wholly

independent of all comparison with those of others.” But this is a fallacy, says

Furbank. Societies were not created for a purpose. They are not utopias.

Furbank points out that Herder’s ‘natural societies’ are just the sort that will

bitterly resent the kind of pluralism Herder avows, where “incommensurably”

diverse religions, adherences, languages, customs and aspirations were able to

flourish side by side in amity. And artificial clamps, tough rules, no doubt

drawn up by bureaucrats, the very things that Herder is represented as

abhorring, would have to be imposed.

Besides, a culturally pluralistic society where different cultures are

indifferent to one another, so long as they pay taxes and homage to a despot, is

just what the Ottoman Turkish Empire was like, and to some degree still holds

even in the epoch of industrialization and nationalism. (Furbank may be talking

about the empire of the transnational corporations whose instrument is the World

Trade Organisation.)

According to Berlin, Herder holds that although every culture is incommensurable

to every other, each is of inestimable value in its own society, and

consequently to “humanity as a whole”. Herder preaches that only persons and

societies, and almost all of these, are good in themselves – “indeed they are

all that is good, wholly good, in the world that we know.”

Furbank is justifiably critical of that remark. He asks, what is this “fabulous

Leviathan “humanity as a whole”? What organs does it possess for receiving

pleasure or benefit?” This is looking for humanity in the wrong place.

“Its real home is in the individual and the single exemplar of the human

species: the human being, whose passion, to use D.H. Lawrence’s words, is “to be

within himself the whole of mankind.””

There is simply no “corporate personality” that feels joy and pain the same way

as an individual does.

“Medieval political theorists…were fond of envisaging the state as a corporate

personality, according to the same legal fiction by which universities and

businesses were conceived of as immortal “persons”. They also favored the notion

of the “body politic,” and theorized as to how some part of this “body” could

represent the whole.”

In an aside, Furbank notes that Thomas Hobbes has cleverly invited a misreading

of the famous illustration to his political philosophy, Leviathan, which

consists of citizens dotted about the giant’s body. We tend to assume that they

are to be thought of as “organically,” composing him, the “body politic”,

whereas in fact, “with his crown and scepter [i.e., the state], Leviathan

represents all the powers that those citizens have stripped themselves of

forever.”

So, what is one to make of the concept of a nation and of “belonging” to a

nation?

Hegel tried to revive the medieval concept of “estates” (Stande), devising a

threefold system comprising a “substantial” (agricultural), “reflecting or

formal” (business) and a “universal” (bureaucratic) estate. For him, “class” was

pejorative, suggesting (precisely) the evils that arise when humans are not

organized in estates.

This gave Karl Marx plenty of opportunity for satire in his early Contribution

to the Critique of Hegel’s “Philosophy of Law”. Hegel’s system of “estates” was

a most accurate account of things as they were in Prussia, and therefore a most

devastating exposé of that dead and spiritless civil society, cut off from all

true political life. Soon afterwards, Marx appropriated the term ‘class’ and

constructed an oppositional twofold system of ‘bourgeois’ (the middle class) and

‘proletariat’ (the working class).

“Class”, Furbank insists, “is a cunning scheme and has driven its claws into our

consciousness deeply. It is not to be shrugged off ...Nevertheless, it seems to

be our long-term duty to try to unthink it; for it can hardly be denied that it

is baneful and belongs with other baneful categories like “race”.”

Furbank finds it puzzling that the world has not paid half as much attention to

what to him is more genuinely mysterious; the relationship of the individual,

not to the state or to the nation, but to the human species.

This mystery is put beautifully by Schopenhauer: “To the eye of a being of

incomparably longer life, which at one glance comprehended the human race in its

whole duration, the constant alternation of birth and death would present itself

as a continuous vibration, and accordingly it would not occur to it at all to

see in this an ever new arising out of nothing and passing into nothing.”

The liberal humanist’s ambition to expand the “we group to which one belongs

already” won’t work either. Mrs. Thatcher’s famous phrase, “not one of us”,

comes immediately to mind here.

Richard Rorty’s Contingency, Irony and Solidarity argues that what prompted a

‘gentile’ (non-Jew) to hide a Jew from the Nazis during the Second War was not

the recognition of “a core self”, a human essence, common to all human beings.

Instead, he said, philanthropic behaviours are always based on exclusion. They

affirm a sense of “we” as opposed to “them”.

Indeed, Rorty, quoting Wilfrid Sellers, says “morality” is simply a matter of

“we-intentions”, the core meaning of “immoral action” being “the sort of thing

we don’t do”.

There are, contrary to Kant’s teaching, no “absolute” moral principles or truths

of reason, all moralities being merely contingent historical phenomena. What we

should be doing is “to keep trying to expand our sense of ‘us’ as far as we

can.”

But in objecting to all divisions of the human species, won’t Furbank be open to

the charge that he is promoting the idea of the species as a monolithic, uniform

and undifferentiated mass?

Furbank points out that those charges have always been strongly political. For

example, Aristotle distinguished between master and slave, between the female

and the slave, all of which have to be assigned different status. Aristotle saw

human beings as means, and not ends. He was also a “division-of-labour” man

almost as much as Plato, for whom it was a model of justice itself.

But even Adam Smith, the supreme apologist for the division of labour had to

admit that the differences of talent is not innate:

“The difference of natural talents is, in reality, much less than we are aware

of: and the very different genius which appears to distinguish men of different

professions, when grown up to maturity, is not upon many occasions so much the

cause as the effect of the division of labour. The difference between the most

dissimilar characters, between a philosopher and a common street porter, for

example, seems to arise not so much from nature as from habit, custom, and

education..”

Again, Furbank contrasts such splitting-up of the human species, whether into

“races”, “classes”, “we” versus “them” or “divisions of labour” with D.H.

Lawrence’s belief, that “the ultimate passion of every man is to be within

himself the whole of mankind”. That carries the implication that, “one can

experience things on behalf of others”.

That seems to me the crux of Furbank’s thesis: that in so far as we can

experience on behalf of others so we can act on behalf of others. “To study

“humanity” seems to require two things,” says Furbank. “It calls for the

examination of diverse cultures, and it calls for introspection.... and these

are part of the same mental act, a matter of asking, “what would it be like (for

oneself) to be so-and-so?”

That is how D.H. Lawrence imagines his dead mother looking out on the Italian

scene, and experiencing it through his own eyes.

 

Everlasting Flowers for a Dead Mother

*************************************

 

All the things that are lovely-

The things you never knew-

I wanted to gather them one by one

And bring them to you.

 

But never now, my darling,

Can I gather the mountain-tips

From the twilight lie half-shut lilies

To hold to your lips.

 

And never the two-winged vessel

That sleeps below in the lake

Can I catch like a moth between my hands

For you to take.

 

But hush, I am no regretting:

It is far more perfect now.

I’ll whisper the ghostly truth to you

And tell you how

 

I know you here in the darkness

How you sit in the throne of my eyes

At peace, and look out of the windows

In glad surprise.

 

 

 

 

===================================================

This article can be found on the I-SIS website at http://www.i-sis.org.uk/

If you would like to be added to our mailing list - please send a blank

email to press-release with the word in the subject

field

===================================================

CONTACT DETAILS

The Institute of Science in Society, PO Box 32097, London NW1 OXR

telephone: [44 20 8731 7714] [44 20 7383 3376] [44 20 7272 5636]

 

General Enquiries sam

Website/Mailing List press-release

ISIS Director m.w.ho

 

MATERIAL IN THIS EMAIL MAY BE REPRODUCED IN ANY FORM WITHOUT PERMISSION, ON

CONDITION THAT IT IS ACCREDITED ACCORDINGLY AND CONTAINS A LINK TO

http://www.i-sis.org.uk/

 

 

 

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Join the conversation

You are posting as a guest. If you have an account, sign in now to post with your account.
Note: Your post will require moderator approval before it will be visible.

Guest
Reply to this topic...

×   Pasted as rich text.   Paste as plain text instead

  Only 75 emoji are allowed.

×   Your link has been automatically embedded.   Display as a link instead

×   Your previous content has been restored.   Clear editor

×   You cannot paste images directly. Upload or insert images from URL.

Loading...
×
×
  • Create New...